Essay
In
A Theory of Justice
, John Rawls
provides a contract theory of the principles of social justice in terms of the
‘basic structure of society, or [in other words] the way in which the major
social institutions distribute fundamental rights and duties [to] determine the
division of advantages from social cooperation’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 6)
. The distributive
justice proposed by Rawls is underpinned by two fundamental principles. The
first principle, which is prioritised over the second, is the idea that
people’s liberties should be preserved in distribution. The second principle is
the idea that any inequality that is permitted should only be permitted on the
basis that it benefits the least favoured in society. This is the Difference
Principle which is arrived at from the hypothetical situation of the Original
Position. This essay will explain this principle and the way in which Rawls
formulates it. It will argue that while the Difference Principle taken from the
stance of the Original Position provides a promising framework for the
distribution of advantages in society, it is lacking in certain areas, of which
this essay focuses on three. Firstly, it does not deal with the free-rider
problem, where those who do less work can benefit from the extra work done by
others. Secondly, it leaves the possibility that the least advantaged are
motivated by envy, which is not a just reason for benefitting from the hard
work of others. Lastly by ruling out the concept of desert, it provides a view
of personal autonomy that is contradictory to its principles.
Rawls
begins his theory by assuming a hypothetical situation which will be known as
the Original Position. In order to arrive at a just system of social
distribution which is also fair and in which everyone cooperates with each
other and is assumed to act justly, one must first remove all biases in order
to come to a common consensus on the good of society. Thus the Original
Position assumes a veil of ignorance in which one is unaware of what one’s
social status, income, religion or natural endowments might be when making
one’s decision. This is so that no one can design the principles in their own
favour or allow them to be influenced by ‘natural chance or the contingencies
of social status’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 11)
. Rawls is specifically concerned with
the ‘principles that free and rational people concerned with furthering their
own interests would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the
fundamental terms of their association’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 10)
. This is known as justice as fairness.
According
to Rawls, given the Original Position, people would choose two fundamental
principles in assigning the distribution of goods in society. Firstly, people
would choose ‘equality in the assignment of basic rights and duties.’ This
argument can be comprehended in two different ways. First it can be understood
in the sense that ‘each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive
scheme of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar scheme for others’
(Rawls,
1971, p. 53)
.
Liberties here include ‘political liberty, freedom of speech and assembly,
liberty of conscience and freedom of thought, freedom from oppression, right to
hold personal property’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 53)
, and similar liberties. The second
connotation of this argument is that ‘social and economic inequalities be
arranged so that they are both reasonably expected to be to everyone’s
advantage and attached to positions and offices open to all’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 53)
. In other words,
there should be an equality of opportunity such that people are not prevented
from attaining higher positions based on arbitrary social contingencies such as
class or social position.
The
second principle people would choose given the original position relates to
distributive justice, specifically ‘the distribution of income and wealth’
(Rawls,
1971, p. 53)
.
Rawls says that people would choose a distribution such that ‘while the
distribution of wealth and income need not be equal, it must be to everyone’s
advantage’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 53)
.
Rawls’ formulation of this principle is known as the Difference
Principle. The second principle, according to Rawls, that everyone would
unanimously agree upon is that ‘social and economic inequalities of wealth and
authority are only just if they result in compensating benefits for everyone,
particularly the least advantaged in society’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 13)
. The idea is that it
is just for say a doctor or a pilot to earn a higher salary as he would be
providing a service to everyone, therefore it benefits the least advantaged
members of society as well. The higher salary provides incentive to complete
the necessary qualifications and investment of time and effort required to
reach the higher position.
The
first contention with Rawls’ argument comes from the idea of incentive. Rawls
agrees, by allowing for some inequalities to exist in society, that the idea of
incentive to encourage people to wish to attain higher positions is important.
However, he ignores the opposite issue of the free-rider problem. As Robert
Nozick says, by allowing the less advantaged members of society to benefit from
the work of the richer, one is essentially allowing the poorer to make claims
on the goods of the richer
(Nozick, 1973, p. 81)
. While the presence
of a little inequality provides some incentive to work, some of this incentive
is taken away by the idea that it would be easier to work less and still
achieve some gains at the expense of others’ hard work. This is the essence of
the free-rider problem. People can choose not to work and be satisfied by reaping
the benefits, even whether very little, of the more advantaged, but the more
advantaged cannot choose to work for their own benefit without contributing to
the less advantaged. Understood in this way, the free-rider problem may hinder
the incentivisation of earning a higher salary. Nozick phrases this in a
similar way by saying that those who sacrifice working for leisure time can
benefit from more leisure but those who choose to work overtime cannot enjoy
the extra goods that they could afford. Even if only a little bit of the gains
go to another person, ‘it is like forcing the other person to work
n
hours for another’s purpose’
(Nozick,
1973, p. 63)
.
Nozick
points out that in such a situation the better endowed are worse off because
they cannot choose to work harder to benefit themselves without forgoing some
of this benefit. He says that ‘the less well-endowed gain more than the better
endowed’
(Nozick, 1973, p. 47)
, and even more than
they would in a situation where there was no Difference Principle. Rawls might
argue that if the difference between the less well-endowed and the better
endowed was not significant, this does not dispute the Difference Principle as
long as the less-endowed are still gaining from the situation. While their
goods aren’t being maximised, they are still close to the maximum, therefore
the situation is less than ideal, however this situation is preferable to the
less advantaged losing out while the more advantaged gain. As long as ‘society
[avoids] those situations where the marginal contributions of those better off
are negative’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 68)
there isn’t a problem. However, this
still begs the question of why the less-endowed should be able to make such a
strong statement to their benefit while the more advantaged cannot. Rawls does
not explain why the better off would willingly oblige to make this sacrifice. A
potential Rawlsian response could be that the better off choose to oblige by
entering the social contract from behind the hypothetical veil of ignorance. In
such a case, when everyone assumes that they could be at the less-endowed part
of society, they formulate a principle that will ensure that the less
well-endowed gain the most benefit. However, this response still does not
justify the idea that the more advantaged in society must willingly, for
instance, sacrifice their leisure for labour that they cannot benefit from
themselves, whilst the lesser advantaged gain a benefit from that labour.
Rawls
gives a range of possible interpretations of the principle of liberty,
concluding that the form he wishes to argue for is the democratic interpretation.
This includes ‘a framework of institutions required by equal liberty and fair
equality of opportunity’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 65)
. This alone
considered without the Difference Principle should include ‘improvements in
society so that people avoid too much poverty and wealth’
(Rawls, 1971,
p. 63)
,
as well as a ‘school system to even out class barriers’
(Rawls, 1971, p. 63)
. Also, Rawls
specifically talks about a free and rational society, therefore not one in
which people are so constrained by poverty that they can no longer be rational.
In such a case, one would think that the difference between the least well-off
and most well-off shouldn’t be so great as to reflects the need for a
Difference Principle. Although there may be many different positions in
society, from low position to high position jobs, there should also be an array
of different opportunities and viable alternatives so that no one is forced to
take up any kind of job. In that case, any wish for the least advantaged to
gain more from people in higher positions must be motivated by envy
(Nozick,
1973, p. 110)
.
This is not a fair basis to make a theory of social justice. The least
advantaged would only want to be more advantaged if unwilling or unable to help
themselves, which would lead us back to the free-rider problem. If the least
advantaged were just those who were unable to help themselves, there would be
less contention, but the theory fails to take into consideration those who are
unwilling. A fair theory of social justice must not allow the choice of some to
work harder for a greater benefit to themselves to be undermined by the choice
of some to refuse to work as hard but still gain a benefit from someone else.
Rather, it seems fairer that the better endowed have the same amount of choice
as the less-endowed as to whether they are willing to make a sacrifice for
those unwilling to help themselves. While Rawls might respond that by choosing
to enter into this social contract, one has a moral and social obligation to
work as hard as others even if they are paid more, there may be no way of
guaranteeing that this is the case.
One
solution to this problem which Rawls rejects is an appeal to the concept of
desert. As David Miller notes, this concept says that people are endowed with
unlimited talents and success depends on the willingness to use them, but also
on personal preferences and decisions
(Miller, 1999)
. The idea of willingness and preference
are key. When a person uses their talent or natural ability in some performance
or activity, they should benefit as long as it wasn’t a fluke or based on
integral luck
(Miller, 1999)
. This gives people the incentive to
work harder and have more entitlement to their earnings. However, Rawls
disagrees with this principle. According to him, natural endowments are morally
arbitrary as they are arbitrarily distributed and are part of a natural lottery
that has more to do with luck than anything else. Similarly, whether one is
born into the least advantaged or most advantaged place in society is also a
matter of luck and therefore shouldn’t be included as a determinant for fair
and equal justice. The closest he comes to describing this is in his discussion
of the principle of liberty. Here, Rawls describes as a situation in which
people with similar skills and abilities have a similar prospect of success
regardless of their initial status
(Rawls, 1971, p. 63)
. This is known as the principle of fair
opportunity. Rawls rejects this idea, stating that there is no way to guarantee
that those talents were not the result, for instance, of being in a family that
supports these better qualities. As Nozick points out though, to take away all
natural characteristics of a person is to ‘denigrate a person’s autonomy’
(Nozick,
1973, p. 65)
.
People adopt and use their skills in a variety of circumstances and often
regardless of their social backgrounds. Nozick’s point seems to be that this
individuality should be celebrated, as each person’s own skill and talent is an
advantage.
Rawls’ rejection of this
seems to be contradictory to the concept of human dignity itself that he is
trying to uphold. The rejection of this expression of individuality seems
contradictory to Rawls’ position that the principle of preserving people’s
liberties should take precedence over the Difference Principle.
In
conclusion, although Rawls’ argument for the Difference Principle based on the
Original Position and veil of ignorance provide some useful insights into how
to form principles of social justice, particularly his concept of liberty, the
Difference Principle itself has some flaws. It allows for the existence of the
free-rider problem where it is easier to contribute less and gain more than it
is to contribute more, thus blocking productive incentives. Rawls doesn’t
provide an adequate guarantee that those who were unwilling to work would not
exploit the labour gain of those who work harder. In a free and rational
society, the Difference Principle shouldn’t be needed if other institutions are
upheld and constantly working to fix inherent inequalities in societies, such
as by reducing class barriers. Any existing wish for the least advantaged to
want to gain more would be motivated by envy, which is not a fair basis for a
theory of justice. A possible solution to this problem would be to include the
concept of desert, which focuses on actual action and willingness to perform.
However, Rawls’ rejection of this concept shows a denigrating view of personal
autonomy which is contradictory to the very principles he wishes to preserve.